Notes Dictated to G.E. Moore in Norway 


Go back to top
Please report any errors using this button!
Report an error

Download/print PDF · Plain HTML

Ludwig Wittgenstein

Notes Dictated to G.E. Moore in Norway

Logical so-called propositions show [the] logical properties of language and therefore of [the] Universe, but say nothing. [Cf. 6.12.]

This means that by merely looking at them you can see these proper­ ties; whereas, in a proposition proper, you cannot see what is true by looking at it. [Cf. 6.113.]

It is impossible to say what these properties are, because in order  to do so, you would need a language, which hadn't got the properties  in question, and it is impossible that this should be a proper language. Impossible to construct [an] illogical language.

In order that you should have a language which can express or say everything that can be said, this language must have certain properties; and when this is the case, that it has them can no longer be said in that language or any language.

An illogical language would be one in which, e.g., you could put an event into a hole.

Thus a language which can express everything mirrors certain properties of the world by these properties which it must have; and logical so-called propositions shew in a systematic way those properties.

How, usually, logical propositions do shew these properties is this: We give a certain description of a kind of symbol; we find that other symbols, combined in certain ways, yield a symbol of this description; and that they do shews something about these symbols.

As a rule the description [given] in ordinary Logic is the description of a tautology; but others might shew equally well, e.g., a contradiction. [Cf. 6.1202.]

Every real proposition shows something, besides what it says, about the Universe: for, if it has no sense, it can't be used; and if it has a sense, it mirrors some logical property of the Universe.

E.g., take φa, φa ⊃ ψa, ψa. By merely looking at these three, I can see that 3 follows from 1 and 2; i.e. I can see what is called the truth of a logical proposition, namely, of [the] proposition φa . φa ⊃ ψa :  ⊃ : ψa. But this is not a proposition; but by seeing that it is a tautology I can see what I already saw by looking at the three propositions: the difference is that I now see THAT it is a tautology. [Cf. 6.1221.]

We want to say, in order to understand [the] above, what properties a symbol must have, in order to be a tautology.

Many ways of saying this are possible:

One way is to give certain symbols; then to give a set of rules for combining them; and then to say: any symbol formed from those symbols, by combining them according to one of the given rules, is a tautology. This obviously says something about the kind of symbol you can get in this way.

This is the actual procedure of [the] old Logic: it gives so-called primitive propositions; so-called rules of deduction; and then says that what you get by applying the rules to the propositions is a logical proposition that you have proved. The truth is, it tells you something about the kind of propositions you have got, viz. that it can be derived from the first symbols by these rules of combination (= is a tautology).

Therefore, if we say one logical proposition follows logically from another, this means something quite different from saying that a real proposition follows logically from another. For so-called proof of a logical proposition does  not prove its truth  (logical propositions are neither true nor false) but proves that it is a logical proposition (= is a tautology). [Cf. 6.1263.]

Logical propositions are forms of proof: they shew that one or more propositions follow from one (or more). [Cf. 6.1264.]

Logical propositions shew something, because the language in which they are expressed can say everything that can be said.

This same distinction between what can be shewn by the language but not said, explains the difficulty that is felt about types-e.g., as to [the] difference between  things, facts,  properties, relations.  That M is a thing can't be said; it is nonsense: but something is shewn by the symbol "M". In [the] same way, that a proposition is a subject-predicate proposition can't be said: but it is shown by the symbol.

Therefore a THEORY of types is impossible. It tries to say something about the types, when you can only talk about the symbols. But what you say about the symbols is not that this symbol has that type, which would be nonsense for [the] same reason: but you say simply: This is the symbol, to prevent a misunderstanding.  E.g., in "aRb", "R" is not a symbol, but that "R" is between one name and another symbolizes. Here we have not said: this symbol is not of this type but of that, but only: This symbolizes and not that. This seems again to make the same mistake, because "symbolizes" is "typically ambiguous". The true analysis is: "R" is no proper name, and, that "R" stands between "a" and "b" expresses a relation. Here are two propositions of different type connected by "and".

It is obvious that, e.g., with a subject-predicate proposition, if it has any sense at all, you see the form, so soon as you understand the proposition, in spite of not knowing whether it is true or false. Even if there were propositions of [the] form "Mis a thing" they would be superfluous (tautologous) because what this tries to say is something which is already seen when you see "M".

In the above expression "aRb", we were talking only of this particular "R", whereas what we want to do is to talk of all similar symbols. We have to say: in any symbol of this form what corresponds to "R" is not a proper name, and the fact that ["R" stands between "a" and "b"] expresses a relation. This is what is sought  to  be expressed by the nonsensical assertion: Symbols like this are of a certain type. This you can't say, because in order to say it you must  first know what the symbol is: and in knowing this you see [the] type and therefore also [the] type of [what is] symbolized. I.e. in knowing what symbolizes, you know all that is to be known; you can't say anything about the symbol.

For instance: Consider the two propositions (1) "What symbolizes here  is a  thing",  (2) "What  symbolizes  here is  a  relational  fact (= relation)". These are nonsensical for  two reasons:  (a)  because they mention "thing" and "relation"; (b) because they mention  them  in propositions of the same form. The two propositions must be expressed in entirely different forms, if properly analysed; and neither the word "thing" nor "relation" must occur.

Now we shall see how properly to analyse propositions in which "thing", "relation", etc., occur.

(1) Take φx. We want to explain the meaning of 'In "φx" a thing symbolizes'. The analysis is:—

(∃y) . y symbolizes . y = "x" . "φx"

["x" is the name of y: "φx" = '"φ" is at [the] left of "x"' and says φx.]

N.B. "x" can't be the name of this actual  scratch y, because  this isn't a thing: but it can be the name of a thing; and we must understand that what we are doing is to explain what would be meant  by saying  of an ideal symbol, which did actually consist in one thing's being to the left of another, that in it a thing symbolized.